The 2019 Labour
conference was largely overshadowed by the Supreme Court ruling on the
illegality of the lengthy prorogation of Parliament. The event found itself
dramatically impacted, and the audience found themselves observing a shortened
version of Corbyn’s speech, which (presumably) omitted a number of key policy
announcements, such as the uncomplicatedly positive move to scrap universal
credit. In the end the speech contained only one new policy announcement. This
was Labour’s new policy regarding the production of pharmaceuticals, which they
have detailed in the accompanying document titled Medicines For the Many:
Public Health Before Profit.
By and large, the
document and policy seem well intentioned - while the driving factor of NHS
woes is simply underfunding, it behoves us to consider other systemic features
of the economy that work against an effective British health system. Overall,
the positives of the document outweigh the negatives. Many proposals on how to
work within the existing framework to deliver better outcomes are thoughtfully
explored, and a rethink on the conditions (or current lack thereof) of
government subsidies for research are needed and given. However, in many
respects, this document misses the mark.
These deficiencies
seem to be attributable to the underlying ideology of the leadership - that
market structures are inherently bad and cannot achieve socially beneficial
outcomes. This leads to an exaggeration of the industry’s failures (though
failures which we should acknowledge); a disingenuous omission of discussion
regarding the UK’s exceedingly successful generic drug industry;
misrepresentation of the nature of the industry; and a naive optimism that
government direction would represent a socially optimal design. These flaws are
not specific to the debate about the pharmaceutical industry, but rather a
myriad of debates regarding the suitability of various industries for
nationalisation. It is also possible that Labour’s policy on the pharmaceutical
industry is not motivated by the unique issues of this industry, but rather the
belief that a nationalised industry is
better than an
industry composed of private companies, regardless of the goods or services
produced and rendered.
A more generous
reader, however, may suppose that the most radical of the suggestions in the
document are simply the result of the application of tools familiar to
socialists to a misunderstood problem, and note that praise should be awarded
the document’s Croslandite conception of nationalisation, which represents an
expansion of thought in the labour leadership’s approach to public ownership. A
still more generous reader may argue that the structure suggested in the most
radical portion is a necessary prerequisite to the very ambitious and optimistic
structure of internationalised, government-led drugs production worldwide,
though in practice this is little discussed in the policy proposals.
As the article is
more positive than negative, it is worth beginning with its praiseworthy
elements. A great injustice is done to the taxpayer when they purchase patented
drugs that were partly the result of government-funded research. As pointed out
by Global Justice Now and Stop AIDS, the taxpayers find themselves paying twice
for such drugs, having paid for both development and having subsequently paid
market prices. Beyond supporting industry in the UK, research subsidies lack
any sort of meaningful mutual benefit. Government should foster our high tech
industries, such as medical R&D, in order to both reap the benefits of
external increasing rates of return (which is to say, enjoy the higher
productivity that high-tech industries enjoy when situated in an environment of
many high-tech industries), and to foster an industry which presents great
capacity for taxation through its high profits. It is particularly important to
cultivate high tech industry as increasingly globalised markets push lower tech
industry to the global south, and, given the necessity of pharmaceuticals and
the predatory nature of the US market, it is important to maintain a vibrant
home industry. However this cannot be the only return the state should expect
in return for taxpayer money. Professor Richard Sullivan at King’s College
London posits that the public sector contributes up to 90% of the intellectual
input of R&D. The scale of the subsidies on offer justifies an expectation
of a tangible return, or greater reciprocity in the current arrangements.
Like the Global
Justice Now and Stop AIDS report, the Labour policy document argues that the
NHS should be charged more favourable prices for such drugs (although it does
note that this doesn’t address the party’s concerns regarding lower and middle
income countries), and suggests the possibility of financial returns on drugs
made possible by the public sector’s involvement.
More interestingly,
however, are suggestions that data collected by such R&D is made available
to the state for use in other state-funded research programs. This idea has
great merit. The underlying principle is simple: work and research made
possible by public funds should belong to the public. The demand is not
ownership of the drug, but ownership of the research that made the development
of the drug possible. This is a fair exchange for public funds. One presumes
that such data, now belonging to the public, would then be made available to
other drug development companies in the UK. The proposal is not completely
novel; arguments surrounding the available of data and research from
universities (themselves great beneficiaries of public funding) have been made
for a great while now.
Access to this data
coupled with anonymised data collected by the NHS secured either as part of an
agreement related to public subsidy or via payment to the state, would make the
UK an exceptionally attractive place to do research. Obviously there would be
concerns about a company’s willingness to collect new data if such data is then
made available to rival companies, but this simply requires that the collection
of genuinely new data - rather than duplications of proprietary data - is
subsidised at current rates, whereas companies that no longer need to generate
costly data that already exists can expect either lower subsidies due to the
lower cost of R&D implied, or the same subsidy but a charge to access this
data, to the same net effect. Such a policy seems like it can only have
benefits, and in any future campaigns that take place in a more normal, less
Brexit dominated, context, this is the kind of policy that should be front and
center.
Relatedly, the policy
document condemns the opacity of price negotiations. It is hard to see how this
lack of transparency regarding the prices charged to each country is beneficial
to social wellbeing, and it is hard for companies to justify it through any
argument that is not immediately odious.
This applies equally
to drugs not subsidised by public funds as to those which are, and hence the
party’s argument for price transparency should be whole-heartedly and
uncompromisingly supported. There is otherwise little to say on this.
The document also
outlines tools - called TRIPS flexibilities - that allow governments to respond
to drugs that are charged at exaggerated prices. The example provided in the
policy paper is the use of Crown use licenses, which allow a government to give
second companies the ability to use a patent to produce a drug at a reduced
price when patents are restricting patients’ access to drugs. This option is
already open to governments, and Labour should have used this opportunity to
highlight the Tory government’s unwillingness to use such measures to the
benefit of UK citizens;the example they give is Orkambi, a cystic fibrosis
drug. The suggestion that the UK increase its use of TRIPS flexibilities isn’t
radical - examples of governments using this tool include the center-right
German government, the UK government of the 1990’s using the threat of them in
price negotiations to achieve a lower price, and the Italian government
recently using the same negotiating tactic. International treaties designed to
protect some aspect of intellectual property, private liberties, or bilateral
trade and investment always include some mechanism to protect consumers and
citizens - if they didn’t, government’s wouldn’t sign them for fear of imminent
electoral failure. Governments that fail to use these features of the treaties
they sign do so at their own peril. That the Tory government is unwilling to
use such mechanisms is not a failure of the current market system, and Labour
is quite right to point out ways in which we can immediately improve UK
welfare, thereby signalling its potential role as a responsible government that
proactively protects patients’ rights to access innovative medicines. This
again presents fertile ground for a future campaign.
Finally, Labour is to
be commended for at least part of its approach for nationalising generic drug
production. It shall be argued later that on the whole, this policy proposal is
misguided, but here let us note the aspects in which it is sensible, and
hopefully provide the direction for future moves towards nationalisation that
the party pursues. The form of nationalisation envisaged here is that of
competitive public enterprise. Rather than creating a monopoly - either by
legislation or through buying and consolidating existing large players - the
suggestion is that the state set up a generic drug producer in order to compete
with existing producers. Many states have done this with many industries, and
it is the most appropriate response to an industry which is inefficient or
moves in directions antithetical to the public good. When shown no contractual
favour, and given the maximum degree of independence possible while still being
subject to Parliamentary scrutiny, such bodies, able to compete on the terms of
the industry, should either fill gaps that the market currently does not, or
otherwise be inoffensive to the industry in question.
It would also be
inoffensive to the public’s well-being. State monopolies are concerning
precisely because they lack competitive pressure to improve or reduce costs,
because of the tendency to bureaucratic madness, and because of concerns
regarding the relationship between private enterprise, personal liberties, and
ownership rights. Also particularly relevant in this context is state
corporations’ general unwillingness to attempt risky but high reward
strategies. This method of operation is arguably justified - the taxpayer
doesn’t want to see the money they contributed wasted on speculative strategies
when it could profitably be used elsewhere (though we should note that we need
someone to pursue risky strategies to drive improvement, justifying the role of
the private company in society). State monopolies in the vast majority of
industries confer no additional advantage to society than a private monopoly,
and is subject to all of the same criticism. Public competitive enterprise,
however, lack all but the latter, and can, at worst, do no harm beyond the
expenditure of the money required to run them.
The case that generic
drug production is such an industry where this action is suitable is not
strong, but this does not diminish the significance that Labour has adopted
public competitive enterprise into its body of policies.
Before we discuss the
flaws of the proposals, it is important to distance these criticisms from other
arguments made against it where those arguments have been fallacious or, more
often, disingenuous.
After the document
was released, a number of drug producers and MPs at the Conservative party
conference argued that the policy amounted to state seizure of private assets.
This is clearly absurd, and an overreaction. The only argument regarding
‘seizure’ of assets that could be made must relate to either the use of TRIPS
flexibilities, or the discussion in the policy document surrounding changing
the conditions of patents awarded in the future.
The former must be
dismissed immediately - a country cannot be seizing assets if it uses features
of treaties that regulate the industry internationally. It is acting within a
framework of law to which the companies agreed when they conducted business
within the UK (and any of the vast number of states that operate within the
TRIPS framework). Further, when Crown use licences are used, compensation
according to the lost potential profit is issued to the patent-holding company.
To call the compensated use of a legal instrument to provide patients access to
otherwise unaffordable drugs a seizure of assets is to lie.
Similarly, changing
the terms on which future production is done does not amount to any seizure of
assets. Labour go to pains to stress that the effect of reducing the length of
patents, or changing the conditions of patents would take time to make positive
change, since these could not be extended retroactively to current patents.
That is - no one is taking anything that someone else could reasonably have
expected. No seizure of assets has been suggested.
The Tories have also
used the opportunity to condemn the plans of nationalisation, aware that this
word tends to evoke the state monopolies of which voters - or at least older
voters - have a very poor experience. But as discussed earlier, the form of
state ownership proposed, public competitive enterprise, lacks the shortcomings
of which they wish to remind the electorate. The response is either a
disingenuous attempt to nip in the bud the idea of public competitive
enterprise before it gains traction among voters, or it is simply the result of
a misunderstanding (perhaps not reading) Labour’s policy proposals.
Let us now turn to
criticism of the proposals. The chief flaw is a misunderstanding of the
necessity of incentives to innovate, and how the innovative side of the sector
interacts with the generic drugs sector. One would not get this impression
reading the policy paper, but there is very little to be concerned about in the
generic drug industry. It is in fact the case that generic drugs in the UK are
four to four and a half percent cheaper than in comparable European states.
This is attributed to the market conditions. In the UK, once a patent has
expired, free market mechanisms are allowed to operate. There are myriad
generic drug producers in the UK and across the EU which sell to the UK market,
and the cheap cost of production coupled with the immense competition within
the sector drives prices down to near marginal cost, as one would expect. This
stands in contrast with the many European states that operate some sort of
central price-setting mechanism, which has the perverse effect of increasing
the cost of drugs compared to what we observe in the market mechanism employed
in the UK. The upshot of this is that a nationalised generic drug producer
would have nothing to offer the UK market. As mentioned before, it would
certainly do no harm, but it would represent a waste of public funds, which, in
the absence of a clear and strong justification for the policy casts doubts on
its desirability.
Further, while much
of the criticism levied towards the innovative side of the industry is
justified (the recurring example of Orkambi was certainly well chosen), much of
it seems to miss the point. In particular, describing enforcement of a patent
as “the largest subsidy” the UK offers drug developers is exceedingly
disingenuous. Would we describe any other industry expecting protection of
intellectual property through the courts as being subsidised? There is no
incentive, in any industry, to innovate if the product of that innovation is
simply replicated elsewhere. Free-riding is anathema to innovation and hence we
expect those who innovate to have their product protected. One can argue about
the appropriate length of the patent protection (currently fifteen to twenty
years), but it is necessary that some operating period is granted to drug
developers so as to drive the development of drugs, particularly given that
such research is massively costly, and profits from generic production (and
hence production in an environment without patent protection) are so slight.
There are at least
two ways in which Labour seem to have misunderstood this. Firstly is the
argument that it would require a period of only five years of monopoly power to
recoup the cost of R&D. This seems irrelevant to the question at hand, which
is that of what period of monopoly is appropriate.
The Labour
leadership’s economics often assumes a naive economic setting principally
directed by some sort of free entry conditions, which is to say that the
expected profit from entering a market should be zero, for if it were negative,
no one would enter, and were it positive, more would enter, thus driving down
the profit. This is the principle that motivates the suggested relationship
between monopoly duration and time to recoup R&D costs. However, even
taking this as the basis of our argument, we should not expect a monopoly
period to last only five years, since drug developers also expend vast amounts
of capital on research that doesn’t yield useful results, an unavoidable aspect
of drug development. To argue that five years is all that is needed to recoup
R&D costs for a given drug ignores the plethora of other costs that the
industry incurs.The amount of actualised profit for any successful drug must at
least compensate losses made in failed developments of other drugs for
companies to even begin to invest in development.
More than this, the
motivation of achieving a free-entry condition is unhelpful, as it is not at
all clear that we should,
, wish to attain it
(though it must certainly provide a lower bound). The issue is rather more
complicated. The ideal period of monopoly power is one which delivers the best
for public health. This must take into account the rate of innovation within
the drugs industry, which improves public health in the long term; as well as
the health of the industry within the UK as a whole, because the sector and the
production chain of which it is a part is particularly large (the UK is the
third largest producer of new drugs) and hence affects the incomes - and therefore
the health and well-being - of so many. Additionally, the UK should be wary of
any decrease in its own drugs innovation sector lest it find itself and its
neighbours relying more heavily on the US industry, which will certainly offer
less protection for patients than the UK industry would, and decrease public
access to innovative drugs in the long term. These effects all provide an
upward pressure on the ideal duration of monopoly that competes with the
downward pressure that lower monopoly time reduces prices faster. This balance
is complicated, and depends on so many factors that one should be sceptical of
any author who offers a concrete number as doing exactly this. This in no way
precludes the possibility that the current situation is suboptimal, but it
should put to rest the argument that we must consider only the time needed to
recoup R&D costs, and that any period of monopoly is unjustified.
The second error the
party makes in this regard is quicker to deal with, both for its simplicity,
and for how often the argument has already been made, making this the far more
egregious of the mistakes. The document states that “patents provide the owner
with market exclusivity so that the patent owner can charge a premium on new
medicines, rather than reducing the price to the cost of production or that of
competitors.” This is undeniably true. This is meant to be read as immoral, or
unjust. Hopefully the argument above convinces enough that the option to charge
a premium is not necessarily bad. But worse is the disapproval that developers
do not charge the cost of production, where it is presumed that this refers to
the marginal cost of production (since the average cost of production changes
depending on the number sold, due to the high fixed cost of R&D, and hence
depends on how long the next drug takes to be developed). As many before have
pointed out, while the second pill on any production line may cost pennies to
produce, the first costs several million pounds. We do not expect the first
person treated with this drug to bear that cost, and nor do we expect producers
to accept a form of industry which can only deliver excessive losses.
One might respond
with the evidence from the document that these concerns are all moot, since
much research is undertaken by smaller firms which are then bought by the large
players. This is not a fatal blow on the above argument, since smaller
companies are aware of the landscape in which they operate. They innovate so
that they can make a profit by being bought - bigger firms in turn buy them to
generate a profit. This incentive structure is by-and-large successful, and any
idea that firms “should” operate at zero-profit is a declaration of how we
would like humans to be, rather than a statement about optimal conditions for
public health in both the short term (that is, cheap medicines) and long term
(which requires innovation).
The party’s criticism
of industry in its current form seems to misunderstand the practicalities of
scientific research - namely the incremental and disparate nature of such work
- and ignores the possibility of diminishing returns.
Two stylistic facts
are employed to criticise the drug development industry as it stands today. The
first is a measure that is employed several times in the document as evidence
of the industry’s waning productivity: the number of new drugs created per a given
R&D spend. This is intimately tied to the party’s fairly consistent
argument that developers do not focus on ‘breakthrough developments.’ But the
fall in the number of new drugs created for a given R&D spend could easily
be for the same reason that the rate at which an apple-picker picks apples
declines over time - diminishing returns to scale. The strategy of someone with
such a task would presumably be to start by harvesting the low-hanging apples,
and having done so, proceed to harvest the more difficult to reach fruit.
Obviously the former would take little time and the latter would take a lot. It
is perfectly possible that as our knowledge of medicine and biology advances,
and as the problems we are trying to solve get more and more complicated, the
advances needed are simply harder, and hence require more resources. If
companies could spend less producing drugs, they would have no reason not to do
so - and if a company chose to spend more than it had to on development,
another company would exploit that. The fact is that drug development is hard
and will get harder. We do not exist in the days where a major breakthrough is
made by accidentally growing penicillin in a petri dish overnight.
‘Breakthrough developments’ are unicorns. The intellectual input of development
and the capital requirement for research in, say, gene therapy or targeted
cancer drug research, is vast. It is no surprise that R&D spending produces
fewer drugs per pound spent now than it did in the past. Perhaps this is
exacerbated by deficiencies in the system, but this is not evidenced in the
document that Labour have published, and I am not aware of arguments to that
effect concerning the industry in the UK.
The second commonly
cited fact is more confusing given the premise of the policy. The authors
assert more than once that “the patent system rewards the pharmaceutical
industry for developing medicines that have little or no added therapeutic
value.” There is presumably a wide literature on the output of pharmaceutical
developers, with a correspondingly wide array of measures that one can use to
assess this claim, but the statement itself seems almost irrelevant for the
purpose of challenging the patent system. A patent on an expensive product that
offers nothing that a far cheaper product does not is worthless. Let these
companies patent their drugs. The NHS and consumers can continue to purchase
cheaper drugs with equivalent effect. One might object that this represents a
waste of resources, but market access should incentivise companies to produce
drugs that people actually buy, and it is not at all clear that research as
directed by the Government would be an improvement - as noted previously, the
UK has a poor experience of state-owned monopolies.
Perhaps this
misdiagnosis of the industry in another context would not be particularly
noteworthy, but for a significant period following the electoral woes of Labour
in the 80s, the party turned towards the belief that the nationalisation of an
industry has to be justified by features of that industry. Viewed in this
light, the mischaracterisation of the industry’s flaws (and indeed the ability
of the state to fix them by direct intervention) lead the party down a bad
road, though it is likely the mischaracterisation results from a desire to
reach a foregone conclusion. This is particularly damaging in this context. The
state is not composed of experts on the country’s health or world health, and
in general centralised decision making removes the ability of self correction
that is of the utmost importance in vital industries.
The injustice of the
current subsidy scheme in its current form is unsustainable, and it is
undeniably positive that Labour have brought this issue to the political debate
(though we should not accept the premise that patents constitute a subsidy
anymore here than we would in any other industry). While it is important to
support British industry and innovation, cultivate a high-tech economy as we
navigate highly globalised markets, and take advantage of external increasing
returns to scale, this cannot be the only reward. Labour offers a couple of
solutions for this problem, all of which are sensible, but what is more
valuable is the discussion being initiated. A financial return to the state is
a positive suggestion, but what is greater for UK productivity is the
suggestion that the state should own the data that was generated by state
funding. It is not suggested in the document, but this data could be sold or
shared with UK developers to increase the productivity of the sector by
reducing unnecessary and costly duplications in research, and increase the
attractiveness of the UK as a country to invest in. This would improve the
outlook of both our economy and longer term health interests by driving
innovation in medicine. This argument is of course multiplied by the
possibility of using data collected and anonymised by the NHS.
Labour are correct in
arguing that measures already exist to improve costs for patients and the
taxpayer, and that they need to be used more. TRIPS flexibilities, in
particular Crown Use licenses, are underutilised, and it seems that other
countries have provided examples of how their use can reduce NHS costs that we
should take greater notice of. A vision of a state more actively involved in
drugs pricing should focus its attention here.
However, even taking
the diagnosis of the state of the industry on face value, the role of
nationalism in its solution seems questionable. Generic drug pricing is
incredibly competitive due to low costs of entry into new medicines. We observe
cheaper drug prices than in most of Europe, and notably those with centralised
price setting mechanisms. Given this, it is unclear what the role of a
nationalised generics producer would bring. Corbyn seemed to attempt to breathe
more life into this proposal more recently by arguing that the cystic fibrosis
drug for which the state has recently concluded price negotiations should be
produced by a nationalised producer, but this seems to only replicate the role
of Crown Use licenses. The ability to achieve what he wants already exists -
why spend taxpayers money creating redundant capacity?
The evidence that the
patent system is deficient seems confused at best. The industry is criticised
both for producing drugs that are hard to access, and for not producing drugs
worth accessing. The discussion on the role of the NHS and NICE (the body
responsible for assessing the number of quality-adjusted life years a drug adds
to an average patient to determine value-for-cost estimates) seems plagued with
inconsistency, with the policy paper arguing at once that the NHS exists as a
price taker, and going to length to explain the various mechanisms through
which price and rebates to the NHS are negotiated (and how they can be used
more), including the voluntary rebate scheme whereby the NHS is refunded for
drugs spending above a certain cap. It is perhaps the case that this confusion
and inconsistency arises from a policy that has been pursued through
ideological motivations, and has imported the talking point of access to
medicines from US political discourse into our own, where it does not fit well.
Perhaps the most
fundamental flaw in its criticisms of the industry are the missteps in
understanding the incentive to invest in risky research. This seems to be
rooted in ideological flaws of the party, which is unwilling to countenance
that market structures and rewards lead to positive outcomes, and picture the
state as the ideal director of important activities. As this is an inherently
ideological position, there is little to say in response, other than the view
of an omniscient state seems unfounded by historical example, and is unlikely
to be one that the electorate shares or should share.
Nevertheless, the
vision of public competitive enterprise should be praised, and it is to be
hoped that this will gather pace in the Labour movement. It is high time that
the party shifts its focus on ownership structures from state monopoly to a
wider array, including public competitive enterprise, as well as cooperative
structures and locally owned firms (as well as accepting the role of markets in
many sectors).
Comments
Post a Comment